Legal Studies Research Paper No. 09/106 October 2009 Julius
Stone and the Question of Palestine
in International Law Ben Saul
JULIUS STONE & THE QUESTION OF PALESTINE IN INTERNATIONAL LAW
Ben Saul*
Much of legal and political significance has come to pass since Julius
Stone wrote on Israel and Palestine between the mid-1940s
and the early 1980s, and in some respects the legal situation of which Stone
wrote has become unrecognizable. The Palestinian Liberation Organization has recognized
Israel ’s right to exist and
in turn Israel has accepted, in
principle, a two-State solution. Israel and Jordan signed a peace
agreement and Jordan relinquished its
claim to sovereignty over the West Bank , in favor of
Palestinian self-determination. The breakthrough of the 1993 Oslo Accords 1 led
to the conferral of limited autonomy for Palestinians under a Palestinian
Authority, sporadically interrupted by subsequent security concerns. Two
intifadas in the Occupied Territories in 1988 and 2000 were
matched by Israel ’s resort to ‘targeted
killings’ and a security barrier in the West Bank . Israel withdrew from
southern Lebanon in 2000 and then from
Gaza in 2005, although Jewish settlements in
the West Bank continue to expand, while Israel maintains a blockade
around Gaza and invaded it again in 2008-09. The
rise of Hamas and the death of Arafat signaled the waning fortunes of the PLO,
while complicating the political situation and hence prospects of any legal
solutions.
While the contemporary political landscape has changed considerably,
Stone’s legal views on the Israeli-Palestine dispute nonetheless continue to
resonate on a number of core legal issues which remain unresolved or
controversial: the underlying right of self-determination of peoples in the
region; the legality of foreign occupation of territory (and indeed the characterization
of territory as occupied); the lawfulness of Israeli settlements in occupied
territory; the applicability of the 1949 Geneva Conventions to occupied
territory and to the conflict as a whole; the use of force against
“terrorists”; and the legal position, rights and prospects of Palestinian
refugees. These are some of the issues which Stone wrote about and with which
this chapter is concerned.
Any contemporary reappraisal of Stone’s views must be careful to weigh
them in the light of the law then in force, and to thus avoid anachronistically
overlaying his views with a lens of current jurisprudence. It must also be
acknowledged that the facts upon which international law arguments are predicated
in the Middle East are, in various senses, political or politicized.
The failure to agree on common historical starting points inevitably dogs not
only the legal argumentation, but the prospects for a genuine political
dialogue and legal settlement.
Stone did not, however, see the conflict as a political question above,
beyond or outside the law, as some States unsuccessfully objected in
jurisdictional arguments before the International Court of Justice in the 2003
Israeli Wall Advisory Opinion. As that Court observed, the fact that a dispute
has political aspects, or is subject to ongoing peace processes and
negotiations is not, of itself, sufficient to take a dispute outside the
framework of law.2 * Director, Sydney Centre for International Law, Faculty of
Law, The University of Sydney. 1 Declaration of Principles on Interim
Self-Government Arrangements, 13 September 1993 in (1993) 4 European
Journal of International Law 572. 2 Legal Consequences of the Construction of a
Wall in the Occupied Palestinian Territory , Advisory Opinion of 9 July 2004 , ICJ, para 41. 1 Electronic copy available at:
http://ssrn.com/abstract=1485056
Stone too framed the issues in Israel/Palestine as deeply entrenched
within existing and emerging legal frameworks, which both constrained and
enabled political actions and choices. He did not give up on the law, as some
are tempted to do when faced with such an intractable, raw and violent dispute;
in 1981 he wrote that he was “aware that many people are skeptical, or even
cynical about the role of law and lawyers in the settlement of conflicts” but
argued that law “may provide some essential guideposts in the process towards
peace”.3
Shifting the guideposts is, of course, a lawyerly art as much as a
politician’s calling, and Stone consciously and unconsciously played a part in
moving them. The ambiguity of some, if not many, of the international legal
rules applicable to the Israel/Palestine dispute must be squarely admitted, and
forms the context within which Stone applied the law in this area.
Indeterminacy is a well known feature of any legal system, but perhaps more so
in some areas of international law, where compulsory adjudication is less
prevalent. The rarity of binding determinations allows a wider range of
possible legal arguments to freely circulate, without authoritative decisions
quashing (or at least authoritatively delegitimizing) spurious positions.
Of course, Stone was deeply conscious of the different facets of the
problem of ambiguity, as he observed in his seminal work of 1981, Israel and Palestine : Assault on the Law
of Nations:
Sometimes… ambiguity of an instrument is a trap set by guile, or a
timorous betrayal for the unwary. Sometimes, though more rarely, ambiguity is a
mark of limited imagination and limited skill in negotiators. Sometimes,
however, ambiguity is not thus dysfunctional to the negotiatory and
pacificatory process. For, on issues where the parties’ positions are beset by
passionate commitments, or by dire threats to their very existence as states,
ambiguity – whether by indeterminacy or double-speaking or self-contradiction
or even mere silence – may be a way of building as yet unresolvable conflicts
into a genuine overall plan of rapprochement.4
What is significant here is that, far from simply decrying the absence
of legal certainty and predictability, which may often undermine the rule of
law, Stone emphasizes the creative possibilities opened up by such ambiguities
in the constructive settlement of international disputes. As Stone further
wrote:
…ambiguity serves the critical purpose of providing, for parties deeply
at variance on basic issues, a framework that can accommodate at present the
specific matters on which they can agree, as well as (for the future) the
movement of their positions from time to time on the critical matters on which
they now differ. Ambiguity of this kind is dynamic. It moves in time between
poles of rapprochement and estrangement, of love and hate.5
In this sense, Stone prefigured the approach of other international
lawyers such as Rosyaln Higgins, President of the International Court of
Justice, who sees international law not as a system of rules but as a body of
norms and principles which are part of fluid political processes and ongoing
dialogue between various actors in 3 J Stone, Israel and Palestine: Assault on
the Law of Nations (John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore and London, 1981),
xii. 4 Ibid, xi. 5 Ibid, xi-xii. 2 the international system.6 Rather than
insisting on its ‘rule-ishness’, international law becomes a framework for
dialogue, for politics, and for resolving difference. So too does Cassese write
in the specific context of the Israel/Palestine dispute that ....
Admittedly, the ‘response’ of international law to [such] complex
problems… is unsatisfactory. On the other hand, one cannot demand from legal
standards more than they can realistically offer: a set of general guidelines,
that must be pragmatically and realistically applied by all the parties
concerned, taking into account… not only the wishes of the population concerned
by also the host of non-legal problems that beset Arab-Israeli relations.7
Despite the strength of Stone’s conviction in the productive application
of law to deep political conflict, and the creative possibilities of ambiguity,
it is important to keep in mind that destructive ambiguity – or destructive use
of ambiguity – is the flipside of constructive ambiguity. This polar trend has
become well known in recent years, as when, for instance, a vague chain of Security
Council resolutions was reinterpreted in 2003 to justify the use of force
against Iraq , 13 years after force
was first authorized in the material context of repelling the invasion of Kuwait .
As in that case, or in other recent cases such as the now infamous
“torture memos” of US President Bush’s post-2001 administration, there is a
real risk that ambiguity encourages a dissipation of the normativity of law
into nothingness, rendering the law merely another tool of diplomacy, to be
negotiated or bartered away as politics demands. Lawyers too may participate in
the dissolution of their own basis of professional authority, when ambiguity
comes to serve as an invitation to instrumental lawyering.
Brian Tamanaha, for instance, warns of lawyers (in the domestic American
context) who ‘manipulate and stretch law and legal processes to their very
outer limits, no matter how far away from or contrary to its underlying
spirit’.8 The result is that legal rules become ‘nothing but tools lawyers
utilize on behalf of whichever side their represent’,9 taking advantage of
ambiguities, technicalities, and loopholes. Such an approach to lawyering
detracts from the binding quality of law, and its certainty, stability, and
equality. The instrumental view of law as a means to an end undermines both
formal and substantive rule of law ideals.10
In his lifetime, Stone’s views on Palestine attracted much
controversy precisely because of the perceived instrumentalism of his legal
arguments in support of Israel . One review of his
book, Israel and Palestine , in the leading
American Journal of International Law in 1982 began by stating that:
Readers in search of a balanced treatment of the legal issues in the Middle East will not find it in
this book…. Israel ’s legal position is impregnable
on virtually all issues separating it from its Arab neighbors. Arguments to the
contrary are recognized only for their defects.11 6 See R Higgins, Problems and
Processes: International Law and How We Use It (Clarendon, Oxford , 2003). 7 A Cassese,
Self-Determination of Peoples: A Legal Reappraisal (Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 1995), 242. 8 B Tamanaha, ‘The Tension Between Legal Instrumentalism
and the Rule of Law’ (2006) 33 Syracuse Journal of
International Law and Commerce 131, 146. 9 Ibid. 10 Ibid. 11 F Kirgis, Book
Review (1982) 76 American Journal of International Law 875. 3
The review goes on to excoriate the book for its polemical tone, and for
belittling, distorting and ridiculing the views of his opponents. Another
review of the same year, in the Annals of the American Academy , describes the book
as a “vicious” and “partisan denunciation” of his opponents, resulting in a
“total vindication of Israeli behavior and unqualified advocacy of the legal
arguments that Israel advances”.12
One technique used by Stone was to discredit legal arguments favorable
to Palestine by attacking General
Assembly resolutions which supported those arguments as not legally binding,
and moreover as the product of a majoritarian world ganging up on Israel . There was indeed a
fertile debate about the legal quality of General Assembly resolutions in the
1960s and 70s, following arguments about “instant custom” arising from the
concentration of State practice in resolutions.13
But Stone’s criticisms here often missed the mark, in that resolutions
were often relied upon as material evidence reflecting, rather than exclusively
constituting, customary law, or being an instant source of law. His approach to
resolutions is also highly selective. On one hand, he downplays their
significance when they do not suit his purpose, as when the Security Council
declared inadmissible Israel ’s acquisition of
territory by force,14 or in UN calls for partition in 1947 as well as for an
international status for Jerusalem . On the other hand,
he invokes them when it suits his position, as when resolutions called on the
parties to negotiate a solution, thus not predetermining legal title to
territory; or implicitly when writing in support of the legal importance of
Israel’s 1948 Declaration of Independence, which itself relied on Assembly
resolutions as one basis of its authority; or when he relies on the similarly
non-binding Balfour Declaration of 1917 as a basis for Israeli statehood.
Legal ambiguity (and the language which creates and allows it) is
ultimately set within outermost boundaries of meaning, limits beyond which the
elasticity of rules cannot stretch without dissolving rules (or norms or
principles) into polemic or pure politics. However wide a discretion, however indeterminate
a rule, there are always zones of reasonableness or plausibility, an often wide
range of possible arguments, beyond which arguments become fanciful, unreal,
contradictory and unsustainable. That zone may be hazy and indistinct, but it
is nonetheless material – unless one accepts a radical deconstructionist view
that international law is so indeterminate that all legal arguments are
possible within it; or alternatively, the view that international law is
irremediably flawed in this context because “it encodes power and… enthrones a
particular series of Western legal values”.15
Many of Stone’s positions on critical international legal issues in the
Israel/Palestine conflict stepped outside even generous zones of plausibility,
on the law as it then ambiguously stood. This chapter deals with some of those
claims, an enterprise which remains important because his views, as an eminent
international jurist, remain influential in some quarters, despite their
tenuous nature or dubious provenance. For instance, prominence is still given
to Stone’s views on key issues by 12 H Castleberry, Book Review (1982) 462
Annals of the American Academy of Political and
Social Science 160. 13 See, e.g., Bin Cheng, ‘Custom: The Future of General
State Practice in a Divided World’ in R St J Macdonald and D Johnston (eds),
The Structure and Process of International Law: Essays in Legal Philosophy,
Doctrine and Theory (1983) 513, 532. 14 UN Security Council resolution 242
(1967). 15 J Strawson, ‘Mandate Ways : Self-Determination
in Palestine and the “Existing
Non-Jewish Communities” in S Silverburg (ed), Palestine and International
Law: Essays on Politics and Economics (McFarland and Company, 2002), 251, 253.
4 the Australia/Israel & Jewish Affairs Council,16 which does not place
them in the context of competing (indeed prevailing) legal arguments and
international opinion.
The purpose of this chapter is to interrogate Stone’s legal positions on
the cluster of related issues identified at the outset of this chapter, rather
than to seek to explain the impulses underpinning them. Certainly Stone acutely
felt that Israel was unfairly victimized in international forums like the
General Assembly, which, through the decolonization process, soon became
dominated by blocs of newly independent and developing States, many openly
hostile towards Israel. Stone accused the UN Committee on the Inalienable
Rights of the Palestinian People of sponsoring “partisan theorizing in support
of” the Palestinian position,17 and it is true that the Committee has been used
as a forum in which to berate Israel, often on rhetorical or ideological
grounds, and without grounding in international law arguments. That, of course,
is inevitable, given its function as a political body within the United Nations;
but abuses of the Committee should equally not be allowed to obscure the
genuine contributions it has made to ventilating the complex legal issues
involved.
It seems that Stone genuinely felt the need to spring to the defense of
a beleaguered Israel and the Jewish
people. As early as 1944, in his Open Letter (theatrically entitled “Stand Up
and be Counted!”) to the Rt Hon Sir Isaac Isaacs (then aged in his 80s), Stone
wrote in response to Isaac’s criticisms of the Zionist project:
I sought in this open letter to consider coldly the heated imputations
which Sir Isaac has for some years cast at his fellow-Jews…. If in places I
have unwittingly fallen short of coldness, I ask the reader to believe that it
is solely because of the grief and indignation of this moment in Jewish
history. I mean the grief of the fourth year of Hitler’s massacre of a helpless
people…18
That dissipation of coldness manifested itself in considerable heat
towards Sir Isaac, as Stone went on to write of his
…indignation that over most of that period Sir Isaac devoted himself,
not to constructive thought and action, but to a bitter, unrestrained and
misleading campaign against his fellow-Jews in the free countries, a campaign
which could not but prejudice the hopes of survival and rehabilitation of
Hitler’s victims.19
Stone openly acknowledged his own positionality in live political
controversies and the prospects for partisanship which it entailed. Speaking of
the Eichmann trial in the District Court of Jerusalem in 1961, which Stone
attended, he wrote that: “Anyone, whether Jew or Gentile, knowing even a little
of Nazi barbarism, must be emotionally engaged with the prosecution in this
trial. But a Jew obviously rather more so.”20 That personal engagement no doubt
informed his view that there was nothing unethical about abducting Eichmann
from Argentina in order to prosecute
him in Israel.21
16 Australia /Israel & Jewish
Affairs Council, ‘International Law and the Arab Israeli Conflict’:
www.aijac.org.au/?id=resourcedisplay&articleID=2149&_action=showArticleDetails&categoryID=26
5 (accessed 8 January 2008 ). 17 Stone, Israel and Palestine , above n3, 6. 18 J
Stone, Stand Up and be Counted! An Open Letter to the Rt Hon Sir Isaac
(Ponsford, Newman & Benson Pty Ltd, Sydney, 1944), preface. 19 Ibid. 20 J
Stone, The Eichmann Trial and the Rule of Law (International Commission of
Jurists, Sydney, 1961), 1. 21 Ibid, 15. 5
The significance of Stone’s Jewish ness to his legal views on Palestine is a question better
left to others, whether biographers or psychologists. But it is clear that
existential threats to the survival of the Jewish people weighed heavily on
Stone, whether it was the threat of Nazi extermination, or the wars of 1948,
1967 and 1973, where Israel feared that its
people would be infamously pushed into the sea. There is no doubt that some of
those fears were well founded, not only because of the geographical
vulnerability of the sliver of land that is Israel, but also because of the
commitment of some extreme groups to accomplish what the Nazis could not. At
the same time, casting the Jewish people as the only victims who matter fatally
undermines the prospects for a just and equitable application, or creative
adaptation, of international law to the Israel/Palestine dispute.
1. The Right of Self-Determination The meta-issue framing the
Israel/Palestine dispute as a whole is the principle (or right) of
self-determination, and its contested exercise by competing national groups or
peoples (Jews and Palestinians) over shared territory. Stone characterized self-determination
as potentially existing where a
claimant group constitutes a people or nation with a common endowment of
distinctive language or ethnic origin or history and tradition, and the like,
distinctive from others among whom it lives, associated with a particular
territory, and lacking an independent territorial home in which it may live
according to its lights.22
Stone was uncertain whether self-determination ‘is already a doctrine of
international law stricto sensu, or… a precept of politics or policy, or of
justice, to be considered where appropriate’.23 He nonetheless put aside
jurisprudential controversy about the legal character of self-determination
and, assuming its legal existence, proceeded to analyze the competing
self-determination claims in the area.
Stone mounted three key arguments on self-determination as it applied to
Israel/Palestine, from the premise that Jews and Arabs (rather than peculiarly
Palestinian Arabs) were the relevant national groups which could claim under
the principle.24 First, the provision for a Jewish national home in Palestine,
as recognized by President Wilson and in the 1917 Balfour Declaration, was the
relevant application of the principle of self-determination in the area now recognized
as Israel.25 Secondly, Arab self-determination in the region was realized
through the creation of Jordan, an essentially “Palestinian” State, in 1949.26
Thirdly, Palestinians were not an identifiable or coherent national
group or “people” entitled to self-determination at least until the 1960s.27
Rather, according to Stone, there were only Arabs who lived in Palestine , but not a shared
political or cultural community of Palestinians as such, and the PLO itself
even sometimes denied the distinctiveness of Palestinians and emphasized
pan-Arabism. Any competing, later in time claim to self-determination by the
emergent Palestinian people from the 1960s onwards could not be seen to
prejudice the stability of existing sovereign territorial 22 Stone, Israel and
Palestine, above n3, 10. 23 Ibid, 10. 24 Ibid, 9. 25 Ibid, 13-15. 26 Ibid,
22-25. 27 Ibid, 12. 6 title and boundaries (that is, of the States of Israel
and Jordan), pursuant to the accepted principle of uti possidetis.
Stone’s side-stepping of the legal characterization of
self-determination is at once too neat and too simple. For whether one sees
self-determination as hard law or discretionary politics, policy or justice
potentially shapes the manner in which ones applies the concept to the factual
situation at hand. Specifically, the identification of the relevant claimant
group, the area covered by the claim, the critical date of the claim, and the
manner of its execution or implementation may all depend on whether one
conceives of self-determination as bounded by rigid or formal legal
requirements, or by less stringent thresholds of flexible application.
The application of the principle of self-determination in
Israel/Palestine is thus contingent on pinning down its legal significance at a
given moment. As a statement of political philosophy, the modern notion of
self-determination arose in the latter part of the eighteenth century,
referring to a cluster of related ideas connected with revolutionary sentiment,
territorial settlement, democratic legitimation, anticolonialism, and minority
rights.28
The principle progressively hardened in the aftermath of the First World
War and under the League of Nations mandates. As the ICJ stated in 1950 in
the International Status of South West Africa case, the League mandates were
created “in the interest of the inhabitants of the territory, and of humanity
in general, as an international institution with an international object – a
sacred trust of civilisation”.29 The ICJ iterated the key governing principles
of non-annexation and the well-being and development of peoples not yet able to
govern themselves; the “ultimate objective” was the “self-determination and
independence of the peoples concerned”.30
Outside the specific League mandates framework, however, the principle
tended to remain a selectively applied “policy line” which was subordinate to
the overriding legal norms of State sovereignty and territorial integrity.31 It
was only after the Second World War that self-determination acquired binding
normative force within the framework of the United Nations Charter,32 although
the precise contours of the principle remained to be worked out in practice
over time.
In this light, Stone’s application of the self-determination principle
suffers from a number of defects. He overstates the historical case in favor of
Jewish self-determination in the area; he understates that cohesiveness of
Palestinians as an identifiable people; he inflates the significance of some
sources and minimizes the importance of others; he fixes upon an inadequate
temporal dimension to the dispute; and he does not grapple with the modern
basis of the Palestinian self-determination claim after the 1967 war.
Stone’s starting point in the 1917 Balfour Declaration is immediately
problematic, since one wonders how a unilateral political declaration by the
imperial British Government can constitute a relevant legal step in the
expression of free political choice by the inhabitants of Palestine – the majority of who
were Arabs. At 28 Cassese, above n7, 32. 29 International Status of South West
Africa case (1950) ICJ, p 128. 30 Legal Consequences for States of the
Continued Presence of South Africa in Namibia (South West Africa ) (1971) ICJ Reports
at 31. 31 Cassese, above n7, 33. J Weiler, ‘Israel and the Creation of a
Palestinian State: The Art of the Impossible and the Possible’ in S Silverburg
(ed), Palestine and International Law: Essays on Politics and Economics
(McFarland and Company, 2002), 55, 78, also argues that self-determination was
not part of positive international law during the League Mandate era and in the
lead up to the establishment of Israel. 32 Cassese, ibid, 43. 7 the time, the
legitimacy of the Balfour Declaration as an expression of the will of the local
population was dubious, given the predominant Arab perception that the
Declaration favored Jewish aspirations, compounded by the escalation of Jewish
immigration to the region during the 1920s and 30s.
Britain’s withdrawal from its mandate in Palestine disrupted a smooth
transition based on the political compromise offered by the United Nations’
Partition Plan of 1947.33 The unilateral declaration of the State of Israel in
May 1948 may well be seen as a realization of Jewish self-determination, but
that, of course, cannot prejudice the equal right of Palestinians to the same
end, arising out of the same League mandate and its sacred trust, and as
distinct from the separate creation of Transjordan. The intractable problem, of
course, is that two peoples were/are claiming the same territorial space,34 and
Stone sought to resolve that tension by excluding the legitimacy of the
Palestinian claim altogether. His approach is deeply rooted in Zionist
aspirations: as Weiler observes, “[h]historical Zionism also advances a moral
justification for establishing a modern State of Israel at the expense of
displacing part of the indigenous population”35 and indeed “territorial
compromise and recognition of a Palestinian right to self-determination
arguably threaten some of the moral foundations of historical Zionism”.36
Palestinian national consciousness was arguably less well developed as a
political project than Zionist consciousness in 1948, and in part developed by
defining itself in opposition to the Israeli State . The imagining of any
national identity is a process of positive and negative construction:
particularly in circumstances of tension and violence, a people’s image of
itself is often manufactured in opposition to adversarial forces, real or
perceived.
But Stone tends to equate a lack of political solidarity or strategic
cohesion amongst Palestinians with an absence of the existence of an underlying
people, when some degree of political fragmentation and social difference is an
inevitable feature of even the most cohesive human group. From the Mandate era,
there has been a powerful discursive construction of Jews as an homogenous
community and Palestinians as heterogeneous and diffuse.37 Yet, as Weiler
notes, “Palestinian nationalism… is characterized by a strong measure of
dualism; a dualism of Arab universalism and Palestinian particularism”.38
Multiplicity of identities, and Palestinian affinity with pan-Arabism, does not
prejudice their coherence as a discrete “people” entitled to
self-determination.
From the First World War onwards, and certainly by 1948, following the
numerous eruptions of violence in the inter-war period, there was a (growing)
expectation amongst Arabs in the region that they were entitled to their own
independent territory and government, in territory in Palestine formerly held
as a sacred trust on their behalf.39 The creation of the State of Jordan as a
partial exercise of Arab self-determination did not exhaust all Arab
self-determination claims in the 33 UN General Assembly resolution 181 (29
November 1947) (33 votes to 13, with 10 abstentions). 34 See Y Dinstein, The
Non-Statal International Law (1979), 149. 35 Weiler, above n31, 66. 36 Ibid.
Equally, “the traditional Palestinian claim that Jewish ness may have no unique
national expression is just as untenable”: infra, 69. 37 See, eg, Strawson,
above n1, 252. 38 Weiler, above n31, 70. 39 On the growth of Palestinian Arab
political consciousness, see generally Yehoshua Porath, The Palestinian Arab
National Movement: Vol I 1918-1929 (1974) and Vol II 1929-1939 (1977); see also
Rashid Khalidi, Palestinian Identity: The Construction of Modern National
Consciousness (1997); Muhammad Muslih, The Origins of Palestinian Nationalism
(1988). 8 area. Arab peoples living outside Jordan could not be expected
to uproot themselves in order to relocate to Jordan ; the
self-determination of those Arab peoples cannot be subordinated within the
realization of the self-determination of Jordanian Arabs who lived elsewhere.
While Stone was writing on Palestine into the 1980s, he primarily limits
the temporal dimension of the self-determination issue to the period between
1917 and 1948, when the Palestinian claim to self-determination in the Occupied
Territories arose as part of an ongoing process both prior to and following the
1967 war. Putting to one side the merits of the Jewish claim to
self-determination in the territory declared to constitute Israel in 1948
(given the contemporaneous challenge by a parallel Palestinian Arab claim
there) – during which time the law was less settled – the most secure basis for
the modern Palestinian self-determination claim lies in its challenge to the
foreign military occupation of Palestinian territory by Israel during and after
the 1967 war.40 That claim is not contingent upon any separate continuing
Palestinian claim to the modern sovereign territory of Israel; any such claim
is now pragmatically unreal, although the right of return of refugees to
Israeli remains alive.
2. Applicability of the 1949 Geneva Conventions to Occupied Territories
Like the long held position of the Israeli Government,41 Stone contested the de
jure applicability of the 1949 Geneva Conventions to the territories occupied
by Israel during the 1967 war (including Gaza and the West Bank). In particular,
Stone argued that the formal conditions of application under common article 2
of the four 1949 Geneva Conventions were not met,42 and thus there was not in
existence an international armed conflict to which the Geneva Conventions (and
particularly the law of occupation) applied. Common article 2 relevantly
provides that
… the present Convention shall apply to all cases of declared war or of
any other armed conflict which may arise between two or more of the High
Contracting Parties, even if the state of war is not recognized by one of them.
The Convention shall also apply to all cases of partial or total occupation of
the territory of a High Contracting Party, even if the said occupation meets
with no armed resistance.
While Stone claims to be interpreting common article 2 in a technical
manner, as if the provision is capable of only one obvious meaning, his
construction of the 40 Cassese, above n7, 240. 41 See, e.g., Israeli
Attorney-General Meir Shamgar, ‘The Observance of International Law in the Administered Territories ’ (1971) 1 Israeli
Yearbook of Human Rights 262. 42 Stone, Israel and Palestine , above n3, 177-178.
43 Ibid, 178. 44 Declaration by King Hussein of Jordan (1988) 28
International Legal Materials 1637. 9 provision is neither literal, nor
consistent with drafting history or the object and purpose of those treaties.
Stone focuses exclusively on the second paragraph of the common article 2 and
interprets the reference there to the ‘territory’ of another State as territory
over which sovereign legal title is established.
In construing a treaty, international treaty law requires that a
provision be interpreted in good faith, in accordance with the ordinary meaning
of its terms, in their context and in the light of its object and purpose.45
The preparatory work (travaux preparatoires) or drafting record may be
considered where the foregoing interpretive principle leaves the meaning
ambiguous or obscure.46 The object and purpose of the 1949 Geneva Conventions
is to ensure the widest possible humanitarian protection in armed conflict, and
where more than one interpretation is possible, the more restrictive (that is,
the less protective) is to be avoided.
Common article 2 contains two disjunctive, not cumulative, elements.
Stone’s insistence on the non-applicability of common article 2(2) to the Occupied Territories avoids confronting
the problem of the relatively clear application of common article 2(1). The
latter applies where ever an armed conflict arises between two State parties47
– on the facts, as between Israel and Jordan in 1967 – and
naturally to any territory which is involved in that conflict. As the
International Court of Justice observed in the Israeli Wall Advisory Opinion
(2003), ‘[i]f those two conditions are satisfied, the Convention applies, in
particular, in any territory occupied in the course of the conflict by one of
the contracting parties’.48 That includes territory in relation to which formal
legal or sovereign title is unclear or indeterminate. What matters is that one
State takes foreign territory by force in circumstances where that territory
does not belong to the occupying State. As leading Israeli humanitarian law
scholar Yoram Dinstein wrote in 1978, ‘the Fourth Geneva Convention does not
make its applicability conditional on recognition of titles’.49 Common article
2(2) is an alternative threshold of application and is therefore not the only
part of the article which applies to occupied territory, as suggested by Stone.
The second aspect of common article 2 does not
restrict the scope of application of the Convention, as defined by the
first paragraph, by excluding there from territories not falling under the
sovereignty of one of the contracting parties. It is directed simply to making
it clear that, even if occupation effected during the conflict met no armed
resistance, the Convention is still applicable.50
Rather, it was intended by the drafters to cover cases of ‘bloodless’
invasion, as when Nazi Germany occupied Bohemia and Moravia in 1939.51
Territory occupied in other ways therefore remains within the protective ambit
of common article 2(1).
Even construing common article 2(2) in isolation, there is some doubt
about Stone’s interpretation of the provision. One literal reading of common
article 2(2) – referring to ‘occupation of the territory of a High Contracting
Party’ – might confirm 45 1969 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties
(adopted 23 May 1969 , entered into force 27 January 1980 , 1155 UNTS 331), art 31(1). 46 Ibid, art
32(a). 47 Israel Wall Advisory Opinion (2003), above n2, para 95. 48 Ibid. 49 Y
Dinstein, ‘The International Law of Belligerent Occupation and Human Rights’
(1978) 8 Israeli Yearbook on Human Rights 104, 107. 50 Israel Wall Advisory
Opinion (2003), above n2, para 95. 51 Ibid. 10 Stone’s view that it is limited
to foreign sovereign territory, since the phrase ‘territory of’ another State
may seem to imply legal title. Equally, however, it could be interpreted to
cover any territory which is effectively under the control of a foreign State,
but where legal title is not held, since in a sense it would still be the
‘territory of’ that State at the time of control. In light of the ambiguity,
the latter interpretation might be preferred since it is consistent with the
humanitarian object and purpose of the 1949 Geneva Conventions in extending
protection as widely as possible, so that inhabitants of occupied territories
are not denied rights due to legal wrangles over where sovereign title to a
particular territory lies. As noted above, in any event, the meaning of article
2(2) is not decisive in applying the Conventions to occupied territory under
the broader scope of article 2(1).
While Israel and Jordan are no longer at war, and Jordan has renounced
its sovereign claim to the West Bank, the legally critical time for triggering
the application of common article 2 is the time at which the conflict commenced
and the territory was occupied.52 Nothing in the peace agreement between Israel
and Jordan purports to cede sovereign title over the West Bank to Israel, and
even it were so, there would be serious legal question whether such cession of
territory would be lawful in circumstances where the Jordanian sovereign claim
itself was in doubt, and where the acquisition by Israel is underpinned by
effective conquest, forbidden by the United Nations Charter after 1945.
The applicability of the 1949 Geneva Conventions to the Occupied
Territories is also confirmed resolutions of the UN Security Council and
General Assembly which were known to Stone.53 While Stone correctly denied the
formal legal application of these sources as determinative of the legal
questions at issue, the resolutions are persuasive iterations of the legal
views of a majority of States. In this regard, it is a principle of treaty
interpretation that subsequent practice in the application of a treaty may
establish the agreement of the parties on its interpretation,54 and there is
very substantial overlap between, for instance, the membership of the General
Assembly and the States Parties to the 1949 Geneva Conventions.
3. Legality of Israeli Settlements in Occupied Territory Even if could
be established that the 1949 Geneva Conventions did indeed apply to the
Occupied Territories, Stone denied that the establishment of Israeli civilian
settlements after the 1967 war was internationally unlawful. Article 49(6) of
the Fourth Geneva Convention provides that: ‘The occupying Power shall not
deport or transfer parts of its own civilian population into territory it
occupies.’ An ordinary interpretation of that provision would seem to exclude
both coercive (‘deport’) and voluntary or assisted (‘transfer’) movements of
Israeli civilians by the Israeli government into occupied territory. As the
International Court of Justice stated in its Israel Wall Advisory Opinion (2003),
the provision
prohibits not only deportations or forced transfers of population such
as those carried out during the Second World War, but also any measures taken
by an occupying Power in order to organize or encourage transfers of parts of
its own population into the occupied territory.55
52 Ibid, para 101. 53 UNSC res 237 (1967); 271 (1969); 446 (1979) 54 Vienna Convention on the Law
of Treaties, art 31(3)(b). 55 Israel Wall Advisory Opinion (2003), above n2,
para 120. 11
Stone’s interpretation of the provision, however, imposed a number of
qualifications on its meaning which significantly raised the threshold for
breaching it. Looking immediately to the drafting history – despite there being
little obvious ambiguity about the provision on its face – Stone placed the
provision in the context of
the heinous practice of the Nazi regime during the Nazi occupation of
Europe in World War II, of forcibly transporting populations of which it wished
to rid itself, into or out of occupied territories for the purpose of
liquidating them with minimum disturbance of its metropolitan territory, or to
provide slave labor or for other inhumane purposes.56
It was, therefore, principally directed against the Nazis’ ‘genocidal
objectives’ in ridding Nazi occupied Europe of Jews and making it “Judenrein”.
Purporting to draw on factors flagged in the ICRC Commentaries on the
provision, Stone proceeds to impose two additional criteria for breaching the
prohibition on a State deporting or transferring its own population into
occupied territory: (1) to impair the economic situation or racial integrity of
the native population of the occupied territory; or (2) to inhumanly treat its
own population.
On the first criterion, Stone asserted that the ‘no serious dilution
(much less extinction) of the “separate racial existence” of the native
population has either taken place or is in prospect’.57 At the time of writing
in 1981, Stone claimed that there were only about 20,000 Israeli settlers in
the West Bank, amongst a population of 700,000 Arabs. At that time, the
settlements were no where near as large as they had become two decades later,
when by 2003 there were almost 400,000 Israeli settlers in the West Bank.58
Perhaps Stone was genuinely unaware that the settlements were designed as part
of a purposeful colonization strategy over time, and believed that they would
remain limited, static and temporary interventions – despite evidence available
to him from at least 1977 onwards59 that the Israeli Government was committed
to the expansion of settlements.60 He indicates, for instance, that some of the
settlements were for purposes of military security, and to that extent were not
aimed at the civilian colonization of territory. Confronted with the
contemporary statistics, however, Stone might have changed his mind about
whether the settlements have diluted or impaired the demographic integrity of
the local population.
A further limb to Stone’s argument was that the situation of the local
inhabitants had dramatically improved, not worsened, since the 1967
occupation.61 This belief may have likewise been modified if Stone had come to
see the severe modern impoverishment of Palestinians in the West Bank, as
documented by major United Nations agencies and the World Bank in evidence
before the ICJ in the Israeli Wall Advisory Opinion. 62
56 Stone, Israel and Palestine , above n3, 178. 57
Ibid, 179. 58 Israel Wall Advisory Opinion (2003), above n2, para 122. 59 Ibid,
para 120; see also at that time UNSC resolutions 446 (1979), 452 (1979) and 465
(1980). 60 Even if the settlements are not prohibited by article 49(6), to the
extent that the settlements were sponsored by the Israeli government, it is
likely that an Occupying Power is not empowered under international
humanitarian law to undertake such activities: E Benvenisti , The International
Law of Occupation (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1993), 140-141. 61
Stone, Israel and Palestine , above n3, 179. 62
Israel Wall Advisory Opinion (2003), above n2. 12
On the second stipulated criterion, Stone asserted that there no
question of inhumane treatment of Israelis by Israel , such as to
qualitatively attract the prohibition on the transfer of one’s own population
into occupied territories. Again, Stone viewed this aspect of the prohibition
as directed towards protecting minorities from genocide by their own
governments, which was not at issue here. Indeed Stone argued that the
provision cannot require Israel to forcibly ensure that the West Bank remains Judenrein,
despite its ‘millennial association with Jewish life’;63 he thought it ironic
that a provision designed in part for the protection of Jews would be used to
limited that group’s prospects of flourishing.
Stone’s understandable preoccupation with the background of Nazism clouded
his appreciation of the wider objectives served by article 49(6), which is
plainly not limited to addressing policies only of the scale or equivalence of
Nazi genocide, but is cast as a much wider protective or preventive provision.
The law of occupation rests on a bedrock notion of trusteeship, which is why a
strict approach is taken by the law to preclude an occupying power from
resettling its own civilians in occupied territory, whether overtly, by
stealth, or even by failing to control one’s own people from migrating there
themselves voluntarily.
Stone’s interpretation of the provision purports to identify textual
ambiguity where there is none, and thus resort to the drafting record where it
is unnecessary to do so – and in a manner which contradicts the plain textual
meaning. Although Stone’s two extra conditions are purportedly based on the
historical background mentioned by the ICRC Commentary, the Commentary itself
does not propose those criteria as factors to limit or qualify the plain meaning
of the provision itself, and the ambiguity identified by the Commentary
concerns the relationship between article 49(6) and the rest of article 49
(which addresses forced transfers out of occupied territories). Indeed the last
sentence of the Commentary suggests that article 49(6) is conceptually
distinguishable from the rest of the provision mainly because it is not limited
to the ‘compulsory’ movement of civilians, and thus also covers civilians who
voluntarily migrate into occupied territories and the trustee-occupier fails to
act.
4. Legality of the Post-1967 Occupation Stone responded to assertions
that Israel was an “illegal” occupier of Palestinian territories by arguing
that Israel was lawfully in control of territory acquired in self-defense against
external aggression.64 Such possession would remain lawful until a negotiated
peace settlement occurred, as intimated by relevant United Nations
resolutions.65 Stone further argued that Jordan did not enjoy legal title to
the West Bank since it had illegally acquired that territory by force in the
1948 war. Since title to territory is relative and no other State enjoyed a
better title, so Israel arguably acquired a
superior absolute title over time.
In assessing these arguments concerning legality, the starting point
must be to separate the jus ad bellum (the law on the resort to force) from the
jus in bello (the law of war or humanitarian law).
The humanitarian law of occupation of the 1907 Hague Regulations and the 1949
Geneva Conventions applies to an Occupying Power regardless of whether the
occupation of territory was achieved defensively or aggressively (that is,
lawfully or unlawfully respectively) under the jus ad bellum.
63 Stone, Israel and Palestine , above n3, 180. 64
Ibid, 51. 65 Ibid. 13
First, Stone is correct that territory temporarily acquired in self-defense
cannot be immediately categorized as an unlawful under the jus ad bellum. Here
much depends on whether one views the 1967 war, which created the occupation,
as defensive or aggressive. Stone strongly argues that it was defensive,
against an imminent Arab invasion; critics would submit that it was
pre-emptive, committed prior to the commission of any armed attack on Israel,
and thus unlawful under a strict (if unreal) interpretation of the law on the
use of force under article 51 of the UN Charter (which permits self-defense
only if an armed attack “occurs”).
It does not follow, however, that sovereign title to territory can be
acquired on the basis of a lawful occupation of territory in self-defense. The
occupation of territory in armed conflict has never been regarded as affecting
underlying sovereign title to territory, and continuing to occupy territory
cannot alone perfect legal title to it. Where the underlying legal title to
territory is unclear, title either by prescription – though long established
possession of the territory – or through some more tenuous principle of
effectiveness (by establishing control over res nullius or territory characterized
by a vacuum of sovereignty) cannot arise where such possession is continuously
contested by other title claimants.66
In the case of the West Bank after 1967, title was initially contested
by Jordan and later by a non-State entity, the Palestinian people, in the
exercise of their internationally recognized right of self-determination, and
which arguably grounds a superior claim to territorial title than an Israeli
claim based on foreign occupation. A concomitant of the prohibition on the use
of force in the UN Charter after 1945 was a prohibition on the acquisition of
title to territory by force, even where force is used in self-defense resulting
in occupation. As the International Court of Justice rightly implied in the
Israel Wall Advisory Opinion, that the underlying historical sovereign title to
the Occupied Territories is unclear is not to the point; regardless of who held
historical title (which was unclear given the intervention of the League of
Nations mandate), its current status remains one of occupation, not Israeli sovereignty.
Secondly, there is an ongoing legal debate about whether it is possible
to speak of an illegal occupation under humanitarian law. Certainly particular
acts by an Occupying Power may be unlawful under the law of occupation. But
otherwise the existence of an occupation is a question of fact; that is,
whether a State places foreign territory under its actual control.67 If so, an
occupation is established; there is no room in that analysis under humanitarian
law to consider whether such control is lawful or unlawful as such. The law of
occupation does not expressly provide any time limit beyond which a continuing
occupation becomes unlawful, nor does it provide any criteria requiring the
termination of actual control and occupation.
Even so, on a progressive view of the law of occupation, a protracted
occupation may become unlawful over time if the Occupying Power can be seen as
having failed to make good faith efforts towards terminating its occupation and
securing the resumption of normalcy. As Benvenisti writes:
an occupation regime that refuses to earnestly contribute to efforts to
reach a peaceful solution should be considered illegal…. no such claim of
illegality would be proper 66 Case Concerning Kasikili/Sedudu Island (Namibia v Botswana ) (Judgment), ICJ, 13 December 1999 , paras 90-95 (where that condition was
agreed by the parties, though not in contention in the case). 67 1907 Hague
Convention IV Respecting the Laws and Customs of War on Land (adopted 18 October 1907 , entered into force 26 January 1910 , in (1908) 2 American Journal of
International Law Supplement 90), annexed Regulations Respecting the Laws and
Customs of War on Land, art 42. 14 as long as the occupant’s conditions for
peaceful settlement of the conflict are motivated by reasonable security
interests.68
Occupation is a temporary, exceptional state, in which sovereignty over
territory does not pass to the Occupying Power. It is therefore implicit in the
law that the Occupying Power, holding territory as trustee for the benefit of
the local inhabitants, should take reasonable steps to discharge its occupation
and establish the conditions for a peaceful return of governance to sovereign
authorities. That implication is further supported by the principle of
self-determination, which is not displaced by the law of occupation but
persists concurrently with it. A protracted, unreasonable, bad faith denial of
the realization of self-determination by an Occupying Power arguably aids in
transforming an initially lawful occupation into an unlawful one over time.
5. Use of Force against Armed Bands Israeli incursions into the
territories of neighboring States have been a periodic feature of Israeli
counter-terrorism policy over many years. Stone argued that Israel’s
cross-border pursuit of armed bands (such as terrorist organizations) based in neighboring
territories is an exercise of the customary law of self-defence.69 Stone also
saw such use of force as being compatible with the prohibition on the use of
force in article 2(4) of the UN Charter, which only bans force “against the
territorial integrity or political independence” of a State – neither of which
was prejudiced by surgical incursions against non-State terrorist actors.70
Such an expansive, militant interpretation of the law on the use of
force is not easily supported by the weight of State practice after 1945 and
certainly prior to the terrorist attacks of 11 September 2001 , which may have signaled something of a shift
in practice (although it is arguably too soon to tell). The bulk of practice
and opinion after 1945 confirmed that self-defense against armed bands on
foreign territory is only permissible where the conduct of those bands is both
serious enough to constitute the gravity of “armed attack” (of a magnitude such
as committed by State forces) and attributable to a State under the law of
State responsibility.71 Such an approach is consistent with the shift towards
collective security after the Second World War, designed to minimize the risks
associated with unilateral resort to force by States.
Where States such as Israel and apartheid South Africa resorted to such
purportedly defensive uses of force after 1945, they were generally condemned
by the overwhelming majority of States, who viewed such actions more in the nature
of unlawful punitive reprisals and as unlawful interventions in the sovereign
territories of other States.72 Nor did the South African justification for
anti-terrorism force on the basis of hot pursuit, extrapolated from the law of
the sea doctrine, find general acceptance.
Contrary to Stone’s view that the prohibition on the use of force in the
Charter only applies to military force “against the territorial integrity or
political independence” of a State, and not to limited defensive actions against
terrorist groups, 68 Benefits, above n60, 146. 69 Stone, Israel and Palestine , above n3, 45-50. 70
Ibid, 50. 71 See Case Concerning Military And Paramilitary Activities in and
against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v US ) (Merits) (1986) ICJ
Reports 14. 72 See C Gray, International Law and the Use of Force (2nd ed,
Oxford University Press, Oxford , 2004), chapter 6
(‘The use of force against terrorism’). 15 the majority of States, and the
drafters of the Charter (including Australia), saw that clause not as a limitation
on or qualification of the prohibition on force, but as a means of
strengthening and extending it, to ensure any use of force, even against
political independence, would be covered.73
After September 11, however, there has been increasing sympathy for
Stone’s position, given calls by the United States and others that a State
which merely harbors or supports terrorist groups on their territory, without
actually controlling or directing their operations, may be responsible for
violence used by those groups and thus subject to defensive military operations
by the victim State. Whatever the policy merits of those arguments – and they
remain deeply contested – at the time Stone was writing, State practice was
clearly not sufficiently consistent or dense to support Stone’s assertions.
6. Right of Return of Palestinian Refugees74 Stone opposed demands that Israel facilitate a right of
return of Palestinian refugees displaced during multiple phases of the
Israeli-Palestinian conflict. Stone asserted that Israel had already shouldered
the burden of taking hundreds of thousands of Jews displaced from Arab
countries and Israel had incorporated a large number of Arabs within Israel.75
He argued that Arab countries should take responsibility for displaced persons,
since most were displaced by Arab aggression rather than by the foundation of
Israel. Further, Arab countries were seen to have manipulated the refugees to
exert political pressure on Israel , instead of
resettling and rehabilitating them. Given the special, internationalized nature
of the situation, Stone also believed that the international community must
share responsibility for the displaced.
Clearly many Palestinians were displaced by fighting ensuing from Arab
‘aggression’, but Arab attacks in 1948 were an immediate response to the
unilateral declaration of the State of Israel, an action then thought to
prejudice the realization of Arab self-determination in the area. Once
hostilities commenced, Israeli (or before it, Zionist) violence was also responsible
for substantial displacement of Arabs (one need only think of the killings of
civilians by Jewish terrorist groups (Irgun and Stern Gang) at Deir Yassin in
1948, which provoked terror amongst Arab civilians and stimulated wider
displacement), particularly as the Israeli military response expanded Israel’s
territory beyond that declared at independence.76 It has become an Israeli
foundation myth to assert that displacement simplistically resulted from Arab
campaigns or strategy, while Palestinians have equally blamed the Israelis for
a policy of systematic expulsion. Neither explanation is historically accurate;
revisionist Israeli historian Benny Morris has chronicled the complex causes of
forced displacement during the 1948 war.77
There is indeed some uncertainty about the legal position of Palestinian
refugees, not only because international refugee law was still emergent in 1948
(prior to the 1951 Refugee Convention), but also because the United Nations
later created a 73 Ibid. 74 See generally L Takkenberg, The Status of
Palestinian Refugees in International Law (1998). 75 Israel and Palestine , 25-26. 76 Jean
Allain, International Law in the Middle East : Closer to Power than
Justice (Ashgate, 2004), 104. 77 See B Morris, 1948 and After: Israel and the Palestinians
(Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1994), chapter 3 (‘The causes and character of the
Arab exodus from Palestine ’); see also Allain,
ibid, 102-105. 16 sui generis legal regime for Palestinian refugees (UNRWA),78
outside the regular framework of the 1951 Refugee Convention. In part, this was
at the insistence of Arab States, who feared that the special situation of
Palestinians would be subsumed within any general framework on refugees.
Paradoxically, the separate treatment of Palestinian refugees has arguably
worked to their detriment, as the UNRWA mandate focused on humanitarian relief
and assistance while undertaking minimal legal protection activities such as
are ordinarily exercised by the UN High Commissioner for Refugees elsewhere. A
factual complication is that many Palestinians have been displaced multiple
times as a result of the successive conflicts.
In international law, a State is required to readmit its nationals,79
which would include Arabs displaced from within the new Israeli State . Such a right was recognized
in non-binding UN General Assembly resolution 194(III) of December 1948, which
resolved that
refugees wishing to return to their homes… should be permitted to do so
at the earliest practicable date, and that compensation should be paid for the
property of those choosing not to return and for loss of or damage to
property…80
The subsequent political impasse between Israel and the Arab States prevented a UN
Conciliation Commission from pursuing these issues81 and Israel has not accepted a
right of return or a duty to pay compensation. Stone’s argument that Israel
accepted Jewish refugees and some Palestinians does not discharge Israel from
its obligations in respect of all persons formerly resident in Israel and
displaced from their homes. In this respect, the causes of displacement –
whether due to Israeli or Arab violence – are not strictly relevant to a
displaced person’s entitlement to the right; rather, the right flows from the
fact of displacement, and the duty is primarily born by the State in which
displacement occurs.
Stone’s call for international burden sharing is, nonetheless, well made
– UNRWA is the seed of such cooperation – but that does absolve Israel of its own
responsibilities. International cooperation also ought not be seen as a means
of avoiding international legal responsibilities. In the Oslo Accords, for
instance, the question of return was left open to future negotiations (since Israel and the PLO were
entrenched in opposing positions in the issue) and there is risk that the
political bargaining process will surrender refugee rights for wider political
objectives. Such trading of interests may well be necessary in finding an
ultimate solution to the conflict, but the adequate participation of refugee communities
in that decision-making process must be assured if the bargaining process is to
be legitimate. As Weiler notes, we are increasingly confronted with dispute
resolution which “takes place completely outside legal frameworks; negotiation
and conciliation substitute almost entirely for any judicial process of
adjudication.”82 Law becomes just another tool of diplomacy, rather than a
framework of principle bounding diplomacy.
78 UN General Assembly resolution 302(IV) (8 December 1948 ). See also Allain, ibid, 120-124. 79 G
Goodwin-Gill and J McAdam, The Refugee in International Law (3rd ed, Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 2007), 3; see also 1966 International Covenant on
Civil and Political Rights (adopted 16 December 1966, entered into force 3
January 1976, 993 UNTS 3), art 12(4); Allain, ibid, 118. 80 UN General Assembly
resolution 194(III) (11 December 1948 ), para 11. 81 Allain,
above n76, 116-117. 82 Weiler, above n31, 56. 17 18
Conclusion
One of the greatest modern challenges to the international rule of law,
its normativity, its legitimacy, and global perceptions of its fairness, is the
question of Palestine – a deeper, more
systemic, and persistent challenge to international order than other
contemporary fault-lines such the war in Iraq , Guantanamo Bay , Abu Ghraib or the
war on terror. The failure to justly resolve the Israeli/Palestinian conflict
infects and contaminates the international legal order as a whole, as it
represents an ongoing denial of the fundamental right to self-determination; the
perpetuation of an endless and repressive occupation; ongoing violations of
humanitarian law and human rights on all sides; the poisoning of relations
between Arabs, Muslims and the west; and the subjection of Israelis and
Palestinians alike to the psychologically debilitating threat of sudden and
imminent mass violence.
In 1944, Stone wrote in his letter to Sir Isaac that:
There are no Arab claims, moral or otherwise, which can reasonably be
held to stand in the way of righting this great wrong to European Jewry…. if
there were some substantial prejudice to the ordinary Palestine Arab from the
Jewish National Home, this too might ground a moral claim. But here… official
British papers testify rather to continuing benefits, material and other, to
the Arab people.83
While this passage appears to reveal Stone’s benevolent concern for the
plight of ordinary Palestinians, it arguably reveals a lack of genuine empathy
for their situation, an inability to comprehend that Palestinians affected by
the actions of others might interpret events differently from those whose
people stand to gain from the events described. Other parts of Stone’s writings
reveal sympathy for the plight of ordinary Palestinians, but usually blame is
squarely allocated to Arab States , or the British, or
the United Nations, or Palestinians, but never to Israel .
In the final analysis, Stone’s writings on Palestine are commendable for
their commitment to the central place of the rule of law in the resolution of
violent, intractable and highly politicized international disputes. But it is
fair to observe that his views are often more like those of an impassioned
advocate, rather than those of a somewhat drier, but more faithful,
international legal scholar. Ultimately, Stone’s views are counter-productive
even from a pro-Israeli perspective, since they have helped to prolong the
dispute, obfuscate and elongate the legal arguments, generate false
expectations amongst Jews, antagonize Palestinians and alienate much of the
international community.
83 Stone, Stand Up and be Counted!, above n18, 20.
There are many errors in this criticism of the work of Julius Stone - far too many to fit in a comment. For example, the Palestine Mandate is a trust. The trust was to vest when the Jews attained a population majority in the territory where it was to rule and had the capability to exercise sovereignty. They met the standard within the Green Line in 1948 and in 1967 when they attained unified control over the remainder of the trust res, the legal dominion over the collective political rights to self-determination vested there too. The question of whether a United Nations General Assembly Resolution has legislative significance under International Law has been largely overstated. The question has been decided by very few courts and has been rejected by many including by the US Secretary of State. The voluntary movements of Jews to settle outside the Green Line do not constituted a "belligerent occupation", and when the settlers are of a people that has been the cestui que trust of the Palestine Mandate, they have had that rights since the time of the San Remo Resolution and the Palestine Mandate. The "Perpetual Palestinian Victimhood" has been repeated so offten that its narrative has become a "poetic truth", that can't be dented by facts, reason or logic. Finally, the alleged "Palestinian People" is an invention of the Soviet KGB dezinformatsiya appearing first in the preamble of the 1964 PLO charter drafted in Moscow and corroborated only by the first 422 members of the Palestine National Council, each handpicked by the KGB according to Major General Ion Pacepa, a defector during the Cold War based on his personal knowledge. This invention occurred at a time when Soviet diplomats at the UN were promoting the elevation of the right of a people to self-determination from natural law to international law. Israel and the US stand in the way of Soviet (and now Russia's) domination of the MIddle East for the purpose of extending its hegemony over Western Europe.
ReplyDeleteIn interpreting the word "transfer", when the agent and the object are the same, a reflexive pronoun is characteristically added. It wasn't in the 4th Geneva convention.
ReplyDelete